Skip to main content
  • Short contribution
  • Open access
  • Published:

Investigative advising: a job for Bayes

Abstract

Background

Bayesian approaches to police decision support offer an improvement upon more commonly used statistical approaches. Common approaches to case decision support often involve using frequencies from cases similar to the case under consideration to come to an isolated likelihood that a given suspect either a) committed the crime or b) has a given characteristic or set of characteristics. The Bayesian approach, in contrast, offers formally contextualized estimates and utilizes the formal logic desired by investigators.

Findings

Bayes’ theorem incorporates the isolated likelihood as one element of a three-part equation, the other parts being 1) what was known generally about the variables in the case prior to the case occurring (the scientific-theoretical priors) and 2) the relevant base rate information that contextualizes the evidence obtained (the event context). These elements are precisely the domain of decision support specialists (investigative advisers), and the Bayesian paradigm is uniquely apt for combining them into contextualized estimates for decision support.

Conclusions

By formally combining the relevant knowledge, context, and likelihood, Bayes’ theorem can improve the logic, accuracy, and relevance of decision support statements.

Findings

Police investigators occasionally seek the support of specialists in various fields. Cases of murder and rape, for instance, prompt the need to utilize all available resources to prevent future offending by the perpetrators, and serial offenses (believed to have a single perpetrator) can prompt the employment of consultants to link the crimes and anticipate likely sites of future offending (or the offender’s “home base”; Rossmo 20002009; Woodhams et al. 2007). The statistical training and specializations of academic criminologists and psychologists make them candidates for such consultancy (Alison and Rainbow 2011). In the United Kingdom (and some other Western countries) law enforcement agencies have such consultants on staff. The task of these professionals is referred to as Behavioural Investigative Advising (BIA).

The field of BIA is young and still establishing professional and scientific standards (Dowden et al. 2007; Alison and Rainbow 2011). The research literature and empirical basis of BIA are rapidly expanding and improving (Dowden et al. 2007; Almond et al. 2011). Investigators have reported that BIA consultancy is useful both as a second opinion and as a decision support tool (Rainbow 2011). This tool aims to be accurate, useful, specific, and falsifiable (Alison et al. 2003). This assures the consultancy is beneficial to police and allows for the product to be evaluated after the investigation.

The advising process can be summarized generally as using the knowns of an investigation to estimate unknowns useful to investigators; for example, moving from the known locations of a series of crimes to the possible residence or workplace of the offender (Rossmo 2000). BIA consultants can assist in locating, describing, and prioritizing suspects by contributing scientific knowledge and formal analysis of “national datasets and other relevant base rate data” (Rainbow et al. 2011p. 37). That is, their contribution is the assimilation of research literature, evidence, and context to optimize decision making.

Due in part to its recent genesis as a scientific field of study, there are a multitude of quantitative approaches used by BIA professionals to arrive at estimates for decision support. The vast majority of these (e.g., correlation, Jaccard’s indices, chi-square tests, logistic regression) may aptly be called “frequentist”. That is, the majority of approaches involve either interpreting likelihoods from frequency data or utilizing null hypothesis significance testing to interpret estimates of unknowns.

Bayesian statistical inference is the algorithmic combination of previous and new data to obtain the probability of one or more causes producing the new data (Gill 2009; de Morgan 1838). This is different from inferring the simple probability of said data being observed (randomly or otherwise), which is the cornerstone of the more commonly used frequentist methods.

Bayes’ theorem formally combines quantifications of one’s pre-analysis information (a prior), some base rate criminological and demographic data (a normalizing constant), and a likelihood of obtaining one’s evidence. As shown in Figure 1, the prior and likelihood are multiplied together and divided by the normalizing constant, yielding one’s new conclusion or estimate (the posterior). This is more generally expressed as: The probability of a hypothesis (H) given an observation (O) is equal to the probability of obtaining the observation given the hypothesis is true, multiplied by the prior probability of the hypothesis, divided by the unconditional probability of obtaining the observation.

Figure 1
figure 1

Bayes’ Theorem expressed in a) probability statements, b) Bayesian terms, and c) investigative language.

Key distinctions between Bayesian and frequentist (also called Fisherian) approaches to BIA estimation are the use of a null hypothesis and the use of prior information. Bayesian logic involves treating data as constant and modelling one’s belief about relationships in the data based on the context of the data and the data, whereas frequentist logic involves treating the data as random, ignoring the context of the information so as to be “objective”, and—typically—evaluating the existence of a relationship from the initial standpoint of the assumption that no relationship exists. Table 1 details key relevant differences between Bayesian and frequentist approaches to statistical inference. Note, however, that some exceptions to these differences may exist, especially when considering very simple applications of Bayes’ theorem and very complex applications of frequentist statistics.

Table 1 Differences between Bayesian and Frequentist/Fisherian approaches to investigative inference

Bayes’ theorem can be effective both as a tool and as an analogue to the logical problems faced by investigators. Tartoni et al. (2006) note that Bayesian analysis is well-suited for nearly all aspects of forensic investigation, and Schneps and Colmez (2013) illustrate the grievous errors that can occur when cases are built solely based on an isolated frequentist analysis of the evidence. For example, calculating a simple 1 in 6 chance of identifying an offender from a line-up versus a 1 in 12 chance may lead one to believe that having more individuals as foils in a police line-up increases the posterior probability that an accurate match was made. Wells and Turtle (1986) noted that this is not the case. They also shed empirical light, using a Bayesian updating model, on the practice of having all-suspect line-ups, which they found increases the risk of false identification.

Blair and Rossmo (2010) tackle the issue of assigning prior probability values for decision support. They argue that a Bayesian approach can improve estimation of guilt, and suggest assigning probability ranges to single or multiple pieces of evidence. They note that this does not solve the problem of assigning “guilt” values to pieces of evidence, but the approach can result in “more systematic assessments and improved investigative decision making” (Blair and Rossmo 2010p. 133). On a cautionary note, when using databases of convicted criminals to estimate guilt, both the Bayesian and frequentist statistical approaches may perpetuate biases in a system of justice. That is, using the “usual suspects” to predict characteristics of offenders could lead to further focus on these individuals at the expense of other potential investigative leads. The Bayesian approach is not immune to this criticism, though it is less vulnerable to the specific claim that its inherent logic is biased to this conclusion. Frequentist approaches assume the validity of a null hypothesis, that is, they assume the predictor and outcome variables may legitimately be thought to not be related. When this logic is used to evaluate a candidate suspect whose prior offenses are used in the model quantifying his guilt, this assumption is grossly violated and the logic of the frequentist estimator is circular. That is, the offender’s statistical relationship to himself is used as evidence against him because the test, in assuming no relationship, finds his relationship to himself “significant”. In frequentist approaches, this is a violation of the logic of the method. In Bayesian approaches this is not a logical violation (since no null assumption is required and the context of the information is adequately incorporated). However, the potential for an offender’s resemblance to himself to make his candidacy as a suspect more likely still remains. The potential for this concern should be considered when using any statistical method to parse local databases for BIA consultancy.

Table 2 presents a procedural comparison of two approaches to investigative advising, taken from Salo et al. (2012) and Allen et al. (in press). These papers empirically compare Bayesian to non-Bayesian prediction for investigative advising. Salo et al. (2012) informs column a. The study compared use of a Bayesian updating model with a dimensional model to link homicide cases using only offender behavioural information (i.e., only details of what the offender did). Both models utilized identical real-world data. The Bayesian approach, by better accounting for absent information, resulted in 83.6% of cases being correctly classified, versus 62.9% by the dimensional approach. Allen et al. (in press) informs column b. The study compared an empirical Bayesian approach to a “pared-down” base rate method of estimating offender characteristics. The Bayesian approach, by incorporating more contextual information, resulted in 74.6% prediction accuracy versus 63.5% accuracy of the base rate method.

Table 2 Procedural comparisons based on a (highly simplified) investigative advising example

Bayesian methods are subject to a disproportionate amount of criticism for being “subjective” and prone to misuse (e.g., Doren 2006). This is due in part to the forthright philosophy of Bayesian analysis, which formally “confesses” that Bayesian estimates, like all other estimates, are a product of, and representative of, beliefs about the hypothesis being explored. Popperian objectivity requires that the statements and evidence be entirely in observable space (Popper 1972). Therefore, provided all the values used in an analysis are thoroughly explained and justified, Bayesian methods are no less objective than their frequentist counterparts (which involve many subjective choices).

Bayesian methods can formally contextualize, and thus improve, frequentist analysis. In the 20th century, insurance companies used Bayesian inverse probability, contrary to a rabidly Fisherian zeitgeist, without knowing that their computations were incorporating Bayes’ theorem (McGrayne 2011). Similarly, courts in the United States have been using Bayesian risk assessments (Donaldson and Wollert 2008; Wollert 2007) while also lambasting Bayesian approaches (e.g., Doren 2006). Conversely, BIA research has largely used frequentist methods to perform a fundamentally Bayesian task. Whatever the reputation of Bayesian analysis, the task and field of BIA are fundamentally Bayesian. A Bayesian approach to investigative advising is therefore the most logical and promising way forward.

Abbreviations

BIA:

Behavioural investigative advising.

References

  • Alison L, Rainbow L (Eds): Professionalizing offender profiling: forensic and investigative psychology in practice. London: Routledge; 2011.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alison L, Smith MD, Eastman O, Rainbow L: Toulmins philosophy of argument and its relevance to offender profiling. Psychol Crime Law 2003, 9(2):173–183. 10.1080/1068316031000116265

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allen JC, Goodwill AM, Watters K, Beauregard E: Base rates and Bayes’ theorem for decision support. Policing: An Int J Police Strateg Manage in press.

  • Almond L, Alison L, Porter L: An evaluation and comparison of claims made in behavioural investigative advice reports compiled by the National Policing Improvement Agency in the United Kingdom. In Professionalizing offender profiling: forensic and investigative psychology in practice. Edited by: Alison L, Rainbow L. London: Routledge; 2011:250–263.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blair JP, Rossmo DK: Evidence in context: Bayes’ theorem and investigations. Police Q 2010, 13: 123–135. 10.1177/1098611110365686

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Morgan A: An essay on probabilities and their application to life contingencies and insurance offices. London: Longman, Orme, Brown, Green, & Longmans; 1838.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donaldson T, Wollert R: A mathematical proof and example that Bayes’s theorem is fundamental to actuarial estimates of sexual recidivism risk. Sex Abuse 2008, 20(2):206–217.

    Google Scholar 

  • Doren DM: Battling with Bayes: when statistical analyses just won’t do. Sex Offender Law Report 2006, 7(4):49–50. 60–61 60–61

    Google Scholar 

  • Dowden C, Bennell C, Bloomfield S: Advances in offender profiling: a systematic review of the profiling literature published over the past three decades. Journal of Police and Criminal Psychology 2007, 22: 44–56. 10.1007/s11896-007-9000-9

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gill J: Bayesian methods, a social and behavioural sciences approach. 2nd edition. London: CRC Press; 2009.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGrayne SB: The theory that would not die: how Bayes’ rule cracked the enigma code, hunted down Russian submarines, and emerged triumphant from two centuries of controversy. New York: Yale University Press; 2011.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper K: Objective knowledge: an evolutionary approach. London: Oxford University Press; 1972.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rainbow L: The UK approach to the management of behavioural investigative advice. In Professionalizing offender profiling: forensic and investigative psychology in practice. Edited by: Alison L, Rainbow L. London: Routledge; 2011:5–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rainbow L, Almond L, Alison L: BIA support to investigative decision making. In Professionalizing offender profiling: forensic and investigative psychology in practice. Edited by: Alison L, Rainbow L. London: Routledge; 2011:35–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rossmo DK: Geographic profiling. New York: CRC Press; 2000.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rossmo DK: Geographic profiling in serial rape investigations. In Practical aspects of rape investigation: a multidisciplinary approach. 4th edition. Edited by: Hazelwood RR, Burgess AW. Boca Raton: CRC Press; 2009:139–170.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salo B, SirĂ©n J, Corander J, ZappalĂ  A, Bosco D, Mokros A, Santtila P: Using Bayes’ theorem in behavioural crime linking of serial homicide. Leg Criminol Psychol 2012. Advance online publication. doi:10.1111/j.2044–8333.2011.02043.x

    Google Scholar 

  • Schneps L, Colmez C: Math on trial: how numbers get used and abused in the courtroom. New York: Basic Books; 2013.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tartoni F, Aitken C, Garbolino P, Biedermann A: Bayesian networks and probabilistic inference in forensic science. New York: John Wiley & Sons, Ltd.; 2006.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wells GL, Turtle JW: Eyewitness identification: the importance of lineup models. Psychol Bull 1986, 99(3):320–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wollert R: Poor diagnostic reliability, the null-Bayes logic model, and their implications for sexually violent predator evaluations. Psychology, Public Policy, and Law 2007, 13(3):167–203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodhams J, Bull R, Hollin C: Case linkage-identifying crimes committed by the same offender. In Kocsis (Ed.), Criminal profiling: International theory, research, and practice (pp. 117–133). Totowa, NJ: Humana Press Inc.; 2007.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thank you to all five reviewers and the editorial staff, with special credit to Reviewer 4 for improving the manuscript's technical rigor. This research was funded in part by the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jared C Allen.

Additional information

Competing interests

The author declares he has no competing interests.

Authors’ original submitted files for images

Below are the links to the authors’ original submitted files for images.

Authors’ original file for figure 1

Rights and permissions

Open Access This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 2.0 International License (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/2.0), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Allen, J.C. Investigative advising: a job for Bayes. Crime Sci 3, 7 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1186/2193-7680-3-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1186/2193-7680-3-7

Keywords